Introduction (Concluded)
The third chapter (Theories and Shifting Domains) inquires
into the sense in which scientific theories in the formal mode identify a
stretch of the world. The contemporary discipline of linguistic theory is an
interesting example to study in this context because of its recentness; we are
able to study its entire history in a stretch to see whether the reality of
human language has come into sharper focus as the theory progressed. After a
brief exposition of the basic joints of the theory, it turns out that even
within its short history the object of the theory has become increasingly
theory-laden for Chomsky (1991) to remark that perhaps there is no such thing
as language.
The
fourth chapter (The Skeptic and the
Cognitivist) adds another dimension to the skepticism just raised. This
chapter joins issue with recent claims from the cognitive sciences that the
ancient discipline of philosophy is beginning to lose its relevance for
understanding human cognition. We focus again on the new discipline of
linguistic theory, which is perhaps the most promising program in the cognitive
sciences. As the work of philosophers of language mentioned earlier highlighted,
the basic classical interest in the study of language has been that humans have
the astonishing ability to talk about the world: the semantic ability. As hinted earlier, the theoretical resources of
linguistic theory seem to fall far short of the philosophical interest.
Having
secured something like a zone of autonomy for the philosophical form of inquiry
in the fourth essay, the fifth chapter (From
Things to Needs) attempts to develop the idea of autonomy by focusing on
the general form of classical Indian philosophy. It may be justly complained
that, unlike Western philosophy, this philosophy has lost its relevance because
it never interacted with the vast edifice of European science. This conclusion
will follow only under the assumption that scientific knowledge over-rules or
replaces philosophical inquiry. A quick look at the origin and form of Indian
philosophy suggests that its goals might not have been to discover properties
of the world at all. A salient goal for philosophical inquiry, distinct from
the sciences, could be to formulate conditions of human reflective needs for cognitive agents to lead
rational lives. The study of needs seems to be fundamental to philosophical
inquiry since its presence can be located even in classical Western philosophy
when it is shorn off its ‘scientific’ goals. Interestingly, the study of the
mind—the contentious domain under consideration—offers some promising evidence
on this issue. In this light, each of the concepts of consciousness, knowledge
and belief may be understood very differently from their alleged ‘mentalistic’
features discussed in the received literature.
The
next three chapters (Yearning for
Consciousness, Ascription of
Knowledge, Beliefs and Believers)
cover the alternative perspective. The chapters exploit the general distinction
between description and ascription. While the goal of
descriptions is to examine properties of objects, ascriptions suggest devices
of personal evaluation. Each chapter thus consists of two distinct parts. In
the first part, we show that the current state of philosophical inquiry on
these concepts is at best uncertain; there appear to be fundamental conceptual
darkness around them. However, each concept turns out to be salient when we
think of them as recommending different evaluative attitudes towards persons
and communities to enable us to get a grip on our inter-personal lives.
The
idea of placing much of philosophical inquiry into the cultural mode raises the
issue of whether the notion of the cultural, as distinct from the scientific,
is a coherent unified category. One way of examining the issue is to locate
some invariant notion of interpretation governing each of the putative cultural
objects. A somewhat detailed ‘anthropological’ study pursued in the ninth
chapter (Varieties of Interpretation)
across rituals, poetry, painting, and music suggests that even the notion of
interpretation radically varies as the objects vary. So, for example, we cannot
say without equivocation that cultural objects have a distinctive aspect in
that they admit of both singular and plural interpretations.
The
perspectives that govern interpretations come in a variety of forms: plurality
of traditions, bounds of space and time, eras and epochs, textuality and
interpretations, multiplicity of languages, gestalt properties, and simply
differences of irreconcilable opinion, often assuming the form of class-war.
None of these are seen in science, say, in theoretical physics. No doubt, there
are scientific disputes, but that is a different matter altogether. Beyond this
general observation of open-ended plurality, human inquiry is too diffused an
undertaking to lend itself to definite categories.
Yet,
we can locate on examination that there are tangible distinctions between forms
of inquiry, even if they blend into one another to mask their identity. For
example, we could make some sense of the distinction between the scientific and
the philosophical modes as above even if philosophical inquiry sometimes takes
a scientific form up to a point. Similarly, there is a perceived sense of
affinity between philosophy and literature as an impressive body of
‘converging’ literature testifies. Focusing on the non-converging literature,
the tenth chapter (Literature and Common
Life) takes up one of the leading issues for this collection of chapters:
where does common life get its enrichment from in the general absence of
scientific reflection? The answer projected in the chapter appeals to the
notion of a text. An author’s view
from somewhere enshrined in a text—Platonic or Shakespearean—enables the
cognitive agent to expand her horizons and transcend her locality.
The
phenomenon of locality and its appeal to textuality is perhaps most directly
illustrated in the case of religions. The eleventh chapter (Religion and Mass Culture) raises the
problem that, if textuality of religions is understood narrowly in terms of
their master-texts, then it will follow that textuality, instead of enhancing
the rationality of the cognitive agent, in fact impedes it. And there is no
doubt, as documented in the chapter with a particular political scenario in
contemporary India, religions can play massively regressive roles. To resolve
the dilemma, it is suggested that we need to broaden the notion of textuality
to include the complex variety of religious practices
that accompany the master-texts; in fact, sometimes there is considerable
cognitive separation between the two. So, it is possible for regressive forces
to propagate hate by securing allegiance of people in terms of meaningful
religious practices.
Given
the variety, richness, and autonomy of forms of human inquiry, it is
difficult—perhaps even morally questionable—to prioritize a specific form of
knowledge. In any case, as we saw, even what is taken to be the pinnacle of
human inquiry, namely, formal science, has only limited role in human life. In
this essentially pluralistic conception of human knowledge, the final chapter (Education for the Species) raises the
issue of the value of this edifice of human knowledge. Sketching the grim
scenario for the survival of the human species, it is argued that much of the
damage can be traced to the adoption of highly prioritized knowledge-systems
ensuing from elite high-cultures. In contrast, the marginalized
knowledge-systems of the indigenous people across the world offer a salient
perspective for saving the planet. The salience of indigenous knowledge entails
a large-scale rejection of elite knowledge-systems. If skepticism is viewed as
a state of mind that rejects dominating knowledge-systems, humans need to adopt
probably the most extreme form of skepticism, if the species is to survive.
No comments:
Post a Comment